The Major Topics of School Algebra

Without any knowledge of the historical background of the logarithm, many students
have come to regard it as another function they need to learn to pass an exam, with no
ap preciation whatsoever of the almost magical property that log x changes multiplication
to addition.

Fixing a base a, a > 0 and a ≠ 1. Then the functions and g(x) = ax are
inverse functions, the domain of f being all positive numbers . Thus

for all x

and

for all positive t

These two relations, which characterize the fact that and ax are inverse functions, are
the key to solving equations of the following type: find x so that . Equations
of this type come up in applications, because nature seems to dictate that natural growth
and decay processes be modeled by exp onential functions , more specifically, by ex and
variants thereof. There is potential for real excitement here as simple carbon dating
problems can be discussed in this context.

Problems about changing bases in logarithms are good for testing students’ basic understanding
of the definitions, but should not be elevated to the status of a major topic.
( Compare the discussion about factoring quadratic polynomials.)

The last collection of functions to receive attention in school algebra are from outside
algebra: the trigonometric functions. These are functions that are initially defined only for
(we use radian measure), so the first order of business is to extend the definition
of sine, cosine to 0 ≤ x ≤ 2π , and then to all values of x by demanding periodicity of
period 2π
, namely, sin(x ± 2π ) = sin x, and the same for cosine. Thus sine and cosine
become defined on the whole number line. They turn out to be the prototypical periodic
functions, because in advanced mathematics one shows that any function f which satisfies
f(x±2π ) = f(x) for all x can be expressed in terms of sine and cosine in a precise sense.
The restriction to 2π as the period is more apparent than real because, if a positive
number c is given, then the function h(x) = a sin(2π x/c) is periodic of period c (i.e.,
h(x±c) = h(x) for all x), and has maximum value |a| and minimum value −|a|. Students
should have instant recall of the graphs of sine and cosine. In particular, sine is increasing
in the interval and therefore has an inverse function there. Similarly, cosine is
decreasing on [0, π] and it too admits an inverse function there.

One of the reasons that sine and cosine are important in mathematics and science is
that nature is full of periodic phenomena.

Once sine and cosine are fully understood, the study of the other four trigonometric
functions becomes fairly routine. Tangent is the most important of these four and its
graph too should be accessible to instant recall. Note that tangent is not defined at all
odd integer multiples of  .

We have mentioned the use of exponential and logarithmic functions to model growth
and decay and the use of sine and cosine to model periodic phenomena. The use of
linear functions to model certain observable phenomena should also be mentioned in this
connection. Generically, some observational data, when properly graphed, seem to suggest
a linear relationship although the data do not appear to be strictly linear due to inevitable
observational inaccuracies. In such situations, one employs the method of least squares
to arrive at a linear function that is a “best fit” for the data. The details of the method are
beyond the level of school mathematics, but the main idea of the method can nevertheless
be conveyed in a qualitative way. The use of computer software, or even a programmable
calculator, to produce the “line of best fit” may be used, with guidance, to advantage to
give an intuitive understanding of this process.

Algebra of Polynomials

Algebra at a more advanced level becomes an abstract study of structure. School
algebra, at some point, should introduce students to such abstract considerations. The
study of polynomials provides a good transition from algebra as generalized arithmetic to
abstract algebra. Rather than considering a polynomial as the sum of multiples of powers
of a number x, we now consider sums of multiples of powers of a symbol X ,



where the are constants (i = 0, 1, . . . , n), and ≠ 0. To avoid confusion with the
polynomials we have been working with so far, we will call such an f(X) a polynomial
form
, but will continue to refer to n as its degree, the as its coefficients, and
as its leading coefficient. The term will also be referred to as its constant term.
As a matter of convention, we will omit the writing of a term if its coefficient is 0. Thus
2X2 + 0X + 3 is abbreviated to 2X2 + 3. We define two polynomial forms to be equal
if their corresponding coefficients are pairwise equal. In particular, two equal polynomial
forms must have the same degree, because they must have the same leading coefficient.
Note that the concept of the equality of polynomial forms is a matter of definition and is
not subject to psychological interpretations. This should help clarify the current concern
about the meaning of the equal sign in the mathematics education research literature.

We now single out a special case of the equality of polynomial forms for further discussion
because it is a delicate point that can lead to confusion. Given a polynomial form
f(X), what does it mean to say f(X) ≠ 0? In this instance, the “0” can only mean the
“0 polynomial form”, i.e., “0” here means the polynomial form whose coefficients are all
equal to 0. Therefore, as polynomial forms, the statement f(X) ≠ 0 means that the two
polynomial forms f(X) and 0 are not equal. From the preceding definition of the equality
of polynomial forms, we see that f(X) ≠ 0 means there is at least one coefficient of
f(X) which is nonzero. Thus X2 − 1 ≠ 0. The reason this may be confusing is that, if
one is not careful, one might think of X2 − 1 ≠ 0 as the statement that the polynomial
x2 −1 is never equal to 0 for any number x. Obviously the latter is not true, e.g., x2 −1
is equal to 0 when x = ±1. In this instance, one has to exercise care in distinguishing
between a polynomial and a polynomial form.

We do not assume that we have any prior knowledge of the symbol X. The addition
or multiplication of polynomial forms therefore becomes a matter of definition, i.e., it
is up to us to specify how to do these arithmetic ope rations among polynomial forms
because such an f(X) is no longer a number. We do so in the most obvious way possible,
which is to define addition and multiplication among polynomial forms by treating X as
if it were a number, so that at least formally, dealing with polynomial forms does not
introduce any surprises. The idea is so simple that, in place of the most general definition
possible (which would require the use of symbolic notations not appropriate for school
mathematics), it suffices to indicate what is intended by a typical example in each case.
Thus let

and

where the and are numbers, and . Then by definition, their sum is



and their product is



In other words, the product of two polynomial forms is obtained by multiplying out all
possible terms and then collecting like terms by their powers. It is immediately seen that,
because the additions and multiplications among the coefficients are associative, commutative,
and distributive, so are the addition and multiplication of polynomial forms.

Why polynomial forms instead of just polynomials? This question cannot be answered
satisfactorily in the setting of school mathematics. The idea roughly is that, since in a
polynomial f(x), the variable x plays the primary role whereas the (constant) coefficients
play a subordinate role, it is conceptually more clear to disengage x from the coefficients
altogether. By singling out x as a symbol X in this manner, we open the way for X to
assume other values distinct from those of the coefficients. For example, in linear algebra,
one al lows X to be a square matrix to obtain the so-called characteristic polynomial of the
matrix. Moreover, it will be observed that the addition and multiplication of polynomial
forms depend only on the fact that the coefficients obey the associative, commutative, and
distributive laws . Anything we say about polynomial forms that depends only on addition
and multiplication therefore becomes valid not just for real numbers as coefficients, but
also for any number systems that satisfy these abstract laws, such as the complex numbers
that will be taken up presently. This is an example of the power of abstraction and
generality in algebra.

In a limited way, we can illustrate the advantage of the abstraction by considering the
problem of division among polynomials. Imitating the fact that the division of polynomial
functions leads to rational functions, we introduce a rational form as any expression of
the type

, where f(X) and g(X) are polynomial forms, and g(X) ≠ 0.

(Recall that g(X) ≠ 0 merely means that at least one coefficient of g(X) is not equal to
0.) We also agree to identify every polynomial form f(X) with the rational form .
For example, 0 is identified with . We again emphasize that as it stands, is just
a formal expression, and it is up to us to give it meaning. First, what does it mean that
two such expressions are equal? Given two rational forms and , we define



to mean



Thus, every rational form is equal to 0. In other words, we rely on the crossmultiplication
algorithm in fractions as a guide to define the equality of rational forms.

As a consequence, “equivalent fractions” is automatically valid among rational forms, in
the sense that for all polynomial forms f(X), g(X), h(X), we have



We also define the addition and multiplication of rational forms by imitating fractions:



One then shows that these operations are well-defined, and that a rational form has
the desired property of the division of f(X) by g(X), in the sense that



Note also that every nonzero rational form has a multiplicative inverse . This
completes the analogy that the set of rational forms is to the set of polynomial forms as
the rational numbers are to the integers.

It may be wise to soft-pedal the well-definedness of the addition and multiplication of
rational forms in a school classroom and use the time instead on more substantive things,
such as the division algorithm and its consequences (see below).

If we were constrained to discuss polynomials rather than polynomial forms, then we
would be faced with the awkward situation regarding the domain of a rational function
: it is not the number line but the points on the number line outside the zeros of g(x),
so that the domain of a sum is the set of the point on the number line outside the
zeros of both g(x) and v(x), etc. But for polynomial forms, we have seen from the above
discussion concerning a polynomial form being nonzero that there is no such awkwardness.

The analogy of polynomial forms with whole numbers leads us to consider the analog
of division-with-remainder among whole numbers in the context of polynomial forms.
This is the important division algorithm for polynomial forms: given any polynomial
forms f(X) and g(X), there are polynomial forms Q(X) and r(X) so that

f(X) = Q(X)g(X) + r(X)

where r(X) is either 0 or has a degree < the degree of g(X). The reasoning is essentially
a repackaging of the familiar procedure of long division among polynomials. This is a
basic fact about polynomial forms in the school algebra curriculum. We note explicitly
that for the division algorithm to be valid, it is essential that beyond the associative,
commutative, and distributive laws, the coefficients have the property that a nonzero
number has a multiplicative inverse.

Prev Next