Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm

7 Bezout’s Identity and the double recursion

It has already been observed that the process of finding the continued fraction expansion of a
rational number a/b (b > 0), involves the same series of long divisions that are used in the
application of the Euclidean algorithm to the pair of integers a and b. Recall that at each
stage in the Euclidean algorithm the divisor for the current stage is the remainder from the
previous stage and the dividend for the current stage is the divisor from the previous stage, or,
equivalently, the dividend for the current stage is the remainder from the second previous stage.
The Euclidean algorithm may thus be viewed as a double recursion that is used to construct
the sequence of remainders. One starts the double recursion with

and .

At the jth stage one performs long division of   by to obtain the integer quotient
and the integer remainder that satisfies . Thus,

The Euclidean algorithm admits an additional stage if > 0. Since



there can be at most b stages.

One may use the sequence of successive quotients (j ≥ 1) to form sequences and ,
as in the previous section, according to the double recursions:





It has already been observed that for j ≥1 and


Bezout’s Identity says not only that the greatest common divisor of a and b is an integer linear
combination of them but that the coefficients in that integer linear combination may be taken,
up to a sign , as q and p.

Theorem 5. If the application of the Euclidean algorithm to a and b (b > 0) ends with the
mth long division, i.e., , then



Proof. One uses induction on j. For j = 1 the statement is . Since by (14,
15) and , this statement is simply the case j = 1 in (13). Assume j ≥ 2,
and that the formula (16) has been established for indices smaller than j. by (13) one has



In this equation one may use (16) to expand the terms and to obtain:



Corollary 3. The greatest common divisor d of a and b is given by the formula



where m is the number of divisions required to obtain zero remainder in the Euclidean algorithm.
Proof. One knows that d is the last non-zero remainder in the Euclidean algorithm. This
formula for d is the case j = m − 1 in (16).

Corollary 4.


.
Proof. The last remainder . The case j = m in (16) shows that .
Since, by the first proposition of the preceding section, and have no common factor , this
corollary is evident.

8 The action of on the projective line

If a, b, c, d are real numbers with ad − bc ≠ 0 and



is the matrix with entries a, b, c, and d, then M · z, for z real, will denote the expression



One calls M · z the action of M on z.

M · z is a perfectly good function of z except for the case z = −d/c where the denominator
cz + d vanishes. If it were also true that az + b = 0 for the same z, then one would have
−b/a = −d/c, in contradiction of the assumption ad − bc ≠ 0. Thus, when z = −d/c, the
value of |M ·w| increases beyond all bounds as w approaches z, and it is convenient to say that



where ∞ is regarded as large and signless. If further it is agreed to define



which is the limiting value of M · w as |w| increases without bound, then one may regard the
expression M · z as being defined always for all real z and for ∞. The set consisting of all real
numbers and also the object (not a number) ∞ is called the projective line. The projective line
is therefore the union of the (ordinary) affine line with a single point ∞.

Proposition 4.
If is any continued fraction, then



where

Proof. Let . Then



The statement of the proposition now becomes



This may be seen to follow by multiplying both sides in formula (9), after replacing with ,
by the column



The matrix M in the preceding proposition is an integer matrix with determinant ±1. The
notation denotes the set of all such matrices. (The 2 indicates the size of the matrices,
and the Z indicates that the entries in such matrices are numbers in the set Z of integers.) It
is easy to check that the product of two members of is a member of and that
the matrix inverse of a member of is a member of . Thus, forms
what is called a group . The formula (19) defines what is called the action of on the
projective line.

One says that two points z and w of the projective line are rationally equivalent if there is a
matrix M in for which w = M · z. Since (i) is a group, (ii)
, and (iii) w = M · z if and only z = M-1 ·w, it is easy to see that every point of
the projective line belongs to one and only one rational equivalence class and that two points
rationally equivalent to a third must be rationally equivalent to each other.

Terminology.
The rational equivalence of points on the projective line is said to be the equivalence
relation on the projective line defined by the action of .

Example 1. The set of real numbers rationally equivalent to the point 1 is precisely the set
of rational numbers.

Example 2.
The proposition above shows that any continued fraction is rationally equivalent
to each of its tails. It follows that all tails of a continued fraction are rationally equivalent to
each other.

9 Periodic continued fractions

In one of the first examples of a continued fraction expansion, it was shown that
[3, 6, 6, 6, . . . ]. This is an example of a periodic continued fraction. After a finite number of
terms the sequence of integers repeats cyclically. If a cyclic pattern is present from the very first
term, then the continued fraction is called purely periodic. Evidently,
is an example of a purely periodic continued fraction.

Note that a periodic continued fraction cannot represent a rational number since the continued
fraction expansion of a rational number is finite.

Theorem 6. Every periodic continued fraction is the continued fraction expansion of a real
quadratic irrational number.

Proof. For clarity: it is being asserted that every periodic continued fraction represent a number
of the form


where a, b, c, and m are all integers with m > 0, c ≠ 0, and m not a perfect square .

Numbers of this form with fixed m but varying integers a, b, and c ≠ 0 may be added, subtracted,
multiplied, and divided without leaving the class of such numbers. (The statement
here about division becomes clear if one remembers always to rationalize denominators.) Consequently,
for M in the number M · z will be a number of this form or ∞ if and only
if z is in the same class.

Since a periodic continued fraction is rationally equivalent to a purely periodic continued fraction,
the question of whether any periodic continued fraction is a quadratic irrationality reduces
to the question of whether a purely periodic continued fraction is such. Let



be a purely periodic continued fraction. By the proposition of the preceding section, x = M· x
where M is notationally identical to the M in (20). Ignoring the computation (9) of M in
terms of convergents, let



Then



or, otherwise said, x is a solution of the quadratic equation

cx2 − (a − d)x − b = 0 .

Remark 2. It is conversely true that the continued fraction expansion of every real quadratic
irrationality is periodic.

This converse will not be proved here.

Prev Next